Making Sense of Bioethics: Column 167: The Corpse Raiders

Subscriptions to this series, as well as reprints, are available from the NCBC for newspapers, parish bulletins, newsletters, or journals. For information regarding subscriptions and permissions, please contact Elizabeth Lee.

Most people recognize the im-portance of obtaining consent before retrieving organs from the bodies of deceased persons. They also understand the necessity of showing respect for those bodily remains following death.

Recent news stories have chronicled the troubling story of a funeral home in Colorado clandes­tinely taking body parts out of corpses and selling them to medical supply companies. One family was horrified to learn that their mother’s head, arms, pelvis, and parts of her legs had been harvested without their knowledge or consent. They and others are now suing the com­pany. The funeral home had been selling body parts to places as far away as Saudi Arabia, and returning containers of ashes to the families that did not contain any actual trace of their loved ones. 

The public outcry following these revelations, and the subse­quent FBI investigation and legal prosecution of the funeral home directors, reminds us how easy it is to transgress important moral boundaries when we fail to respect the remains of the deceased.

Indeed, legal measures can re­mind us of our duties towards the dead, whether through laws that criminalize grave robbing, for ex­ample, or those forbidding the use of executed persons’ bodies for research. A few years ago, Chi­nese officials were timing the capital punishment of their pris­oners in order to harvest their organs as soon as well-paying foreigners had arrived in Chinese hospitals to receive those trans­planted body parts. International pressure quickly mounted to ban the practice. 

While it is clear that we shouldn’t kill others for the pur­pose of obtaining their organs or body parts, it should be equally clear that when an intentional act of killing has already taken place, and a cadaver is available, valid informed consent is still required prior to harvesting bodily tissues. All ethically sound research in­volving human subjects is predi­cated upon informed consent, which needs to be given either by the donors themselves before they die, or by their duly ap­pointed proxy, acting on behalf of, and in the best interests of, the deceased individual.

When it comes to extracting cells or organs from the corpse of a deceased child at an abortion clinic, however, these ethical re­quirements for consent cannot legitimately be satisfied. 

Some have been tempted to argue that aborted children “would have consented” to organ donation if they had been given the chance, since those organs are no longer needed by them after death. But if the justification for harvesting fetal organs is alleged to be the im­plied consent of the child, this has to be characterized as a false, even vio­lent, presumption. The activity of harvesting tissues under these cir­cumstances would only exacerbate the original evil act that terminated the child’s life. Taking cells or tissues without consent would be a callous extension of the original desecration of his or her bodily life.

Additionally, it is important to recognize that even if the mother of an intentionally aborted child were to sign the dotted line saying she granted her permission for the baby’s cells and organs to be donated, that consent would necessarily be null and void. Because she arranged for the taking of the child’s life, she already categorically demonstrated that she does not have the child’s best inter­ests in mind. From the ethical van­tage point, she disqualifies herself from being able to provide valid con­sent on behalf of her now-deceased child by the very decision to have the abortion in the first place.

While the action of taking bodily tissues without consent would be a lesser evil than the act of killing, this does not lead to the conclusion that we can therefore permit or encourage fetal corpse raiding at abortion clinics simply because we have some good use in mind, like pushing forward the fron­tiers of biological knowledge, or pro­ducing a new vaccine or even devel­oping an important therapy for a se­rious disease.

Wherever cells from directly aborted fetuses are used in research or product development, alternative and ethically non-controversial cell sources should instead be pursued, using, for example, cells obtained from routine surgeries like the re­moval of an appendix, or foreskin removal during newborn circumci­sion, or fetal remains following a spontaneous miscarriage, after valid informed consent is able to be prop­erly obtained from the parents. Con­sent given after the natural loss of a pregnancy would be analogous to granting permission for an organ do­nation from a couple’s naturally de­ceased newborn.

Even though significant scien­tific breakthroughs may have oc­curred in the past using illicitly gained cells and tissues from direct abor­tions, this cannot ethically sanitize this approach to tissue pro­curement, nor justify the continuation of the practice in the future. In fact, outl-awing the use of the remains of abortion victims by scientists and researchers would be a small but highly important first step towards showing proper societal respect for the many unborn children who un­justly perish in abortion clinics today.

Copyright © 2020, The National Catholic Bioethics Center, Philadelphia, PA. All rights reserved.